Population Policies, Strategies for Fertility Control in
Population-wide fertility control has a history of both success and failure. That history has been fraught with ethical dilemmas rooted in issues of autonomy, responsibility, choice, community, the significance of reproduction, and the meaning of life, among many others, occurring in the context of a wide range of practical policies designed to limit or sometimes increase human reproduction.
Many early cultures, both Western and non-Western, have been aware of population pressures and have made attempts to prevent excessive population growth. However, the contemporary history of fertility control, responding to the economist Thomas Robert Malthus's (1960 [1798]) warnings, began in earnest in the mid-1960s, when some of the world's most populous nations, especially India and China, became aware of skyrocketing growth rates. From the mid-nineteenth century on, death rates began to decline. Developments in public sanitation, immunization, antibiotics, and medical technology started to reduce infant and child mortality and lengthen the average life span. Average family size in many cultures increased, and more offspring survived to reproductive age. In the latter half of the twentieth century the world's population doubled in two generations, increasing from 3 billion in 1960 to 6 billion in 1999, and estimates of the population in 2050 range from 9 billion to 12 billion.
Despite these estimates of uncontrolled growth, in the early years of the twenty-first century global population growth rates began to decline, particularly in Europe, where by 2003 at least fourteen countries had below-replacement rates (that is, below 2.1 children per woman), in some cases well below that number. Average fertility rates in the less developed countries also fell, declining from 6.0 in the late 1960s, when fears of a “population explosion” were coming to the fore, to about 2.9 in 2003. Disputes over population policies and strategies for fertility control have continued to rage, although they have been tempered in the developed countries by the mistaken popular perception in which declining growth rates are conflated with declining growth. Despite declining fertility rates, absolute population growth remains high as a result of both above-replacement birthrates in many populous parts of the world and enormous population momentum.
ETHICAL ISSUES IN POPULATION-CONTROL PROGRAMS AND POLICIES
The ethical issues raised by population-control programs are of two principal kinds: those concerned with specific means for controlling population growth and those that challenge the objective of limiting human fertility. The earlier population-control programs have been more vulnerable to criticism about the means used for limiting fertility; contemporary policies raise questions about the overall objectives of fertility control.
Early Programs: India and China
In 1975, concerned by the prospect of uncontrolled population growth in an already poor country, India launched a vigorous population-control program that encouraged vasectomy, a comparatively simple and inexpensive method for permanent fertility control. The program in India employed a broad system of incentives and penalties to secure cooperation. Its critics often focused on the violations of individual rights and procreative liberty it seemed to involve, especially when nonvoluntary or semivoluntary means were used to elicit consent, for example, “bribing” men Page 2467 | Top of Articlewith transistor radios (as was alleged) or imposing such penalties as middle-of-the-night roundups coupled with fines, denial of benefits and wages, and denial of educational opportunities. Hostility to the sterilization program was so substantial that it contributed to the downfall of Indira Gandhi's government in 1976, and the program essentially was dropped without an effective replacement.
In China concern with population growth also began in the mid-1960s, but it was not until 1979 that the country instituted an effective if controversial population-control program. Dubbed the “one-child” policy, that program introduced a system of birth limitations that was imposed both in urban areas and less effectively in rural areas: with some exceptions, couples were permitted to have only a single child. The few exceptions were made for couples whose first child died or was disabled and in some rural areas for couples whose first child was a girl or who were members of a non-Han minority group. The one-child policy was imposed by means of a system of birth permits and local supervision of the menstrual cycles of village women, separate residences for young couples in different cities, delayed marriage ages, and the required use of indwelling contraceptives (especially the intrauterine device [IUD]) and required or forced abortion for supernumerary pregnancies.
Observers outside China typically identified two principal moral problems in the one-child policy: the sometimes draconian means by which regulations and penalties were imposed and the consequences for females in a culture with strong preferences for male offspring, including selective female abortion, female infanticide, and female abandonment and out-adoption. The one-child policy is still officially in force, but China has permitted considerable relaxation of it—in particular allowing two children for couples in which both the husband and the wife are only children and for couples who are able to pay a fine for a second child.
Although India's and China's population-control programs appear to have involved similar ethical abuses, including mandatory contraception and severe penalties for extranumerary children, there is a substantial ethical difference between them. India's system was a targeted scheme that worked by profiling categories of individuals on whom pressure for nonreproduction was to be put, and it was satisfied when a preset proportion of “acceptors” complied. China's policy, in contrast, has been imposed in a comparatively egalitarian way: the few exceptions aside, China's policy stipulated that at least in principle all couples were limited to have only one child. While China's policy was not easy to impose, especially at the outset, and the total fertility rate did not drop below two children per woman until 1990, the policy was egalitarian in intent. However, in their haste to expose excesses, such as forced abortion and female abandonment, outside critics typically have failed to notice the ethical conundrum at the center of China's policy: although it is the most restrictive coercive population-limitation policy in any country, it has also been at least in principle the most fair.
Population policies in the developed world have typically but not always stressed voluntary fertility reduction. Zero population growth became a rallying cry and the name of an influential organization and an international family-planning movement dedicated to encouraging couples to have only two children. Indeed average family size in the United States and other developed nations declined dramatically to just above the replacement level. There has been some concern in the United States about manipulative and coercive fertility-control programs that have been suggested, recommended, or put into practice for various minority groups (e.g., sterilization programs for Puerto Rican and Native American women that involved inadequate consent and proposals for bonuses or bribes to encourage black women on welfare to accept the hormonal implant Norplant), but in general the developed nations have proceeded through the stages of the demographic transition, going from high birthrates and death rates to high birthrates and low death rates to low birthrates and low death rates at which population growth again stabilizes largely as a result of voluntary fertility control.
Development-Based Policies
After denouncing abuses in policies such as those of India and China and other nations that attempted to limit population growth by nonvoluntary means, international watch groups turned their attention to the pronounced association between more developed economies and lower fertility rates. With the once-a-decade United Nations Conference on Population and Development in 1994 in Cairo, population policy began to shift toward encouraging development, which was understood to involve both macroeconomic changes, such as moving from agrarian to industrial economies, improving infrastructure, and shifting the balance of trade to greater proportions of export commodities, and changes in social agendas, especially more education for girls and improved economic status for women. With that shift would come the benefits of a modern consumer society, it was argued, with its advanced health care, social security policies, and other institutions, and people no longer would need to have many children to provide farm labor, foraging, or care and economic support in their old age.
The effort in the new development-based policies was understood as being aimed at stimulating mechanisms that would bring about the demographic transition in countries that had not undergone it, and so birthrates would drop, as death rates already had, and population growth would “level out” at a low, steady, globally supportable rate of about 2.1 children per woman. Because women in underdeveloped countries with high Page 2468 | Top of Articlebirthrates routinely reported having on average about two more children than they wanted, changes in the economic environment would make it possible for them to reduce fertility to accord with their desires.
Development-based fertility-lowering policies counted among their ethical advantages the fact that people in advanced industrial nations were willing to share a lifestyle—higher development with low fertility and small family size—that had brought them material advantages and they were willing to foot much of the bill. Developed societies offered better nutrition, better health care, better infant and child survival rates, better education, better jobs, longer life spans, and better security in old age; those advantages were to be made possible for developing countries as well, and in the process fertility rates would decline. Development-based population policies also seemed to have another moral advantage: they were aimed not at directly controlling population or restricting individuals' fertility but instead at changing people's background circumstances for the better, thus allowing them to choose to have fewer children. They seemed to have the moral advantage of favoring individual choice rather than manipulation (as in the Indian vasectomy-targeting scheme) or coercion (as in China's one-child policy).
However, development-based strategies for fertility reduction have raised at least three moral dilemmas. First, they function by disrupting existing cultures, changing traditional agrarian lifestyles into wage-labor ones, often leading rural villagers into the cities and the life of the urban poor and in the process changing gender roles, parent-child relationships, and community structures. Second, they move resources from developed countries into the economic restructuring of less developed, high-fertility countries, not always in efficient ways, and in doing so often bring with them alien cultural and economic values. Third, those models may have counter-productive results: even if they reduce fertility, they may increase consumption, thus undercutting the Malthusian argument for population control. They exacerbate rather than reduce the so-called tragedy of the commons, in which individuals in economic competition exploit resources for their self-interest and thus make communal restraint impossible. In terms of global resources and environmental impact, the original Malthusian rationale for population control, China's success with its one-child policy, for example, will be negated if all those single children want refrigerators and cars.
Reproductive Health Models
Favored in programs in many countries in the early twenty-first century, reproductive health models of fertility control try to avoid many of the ethical problems associated with the early population-control programs and the development model. They avoid the targeting of “acceptors,” instead attempting to provide access to contraception and reproductive health care to everyone. They further avoid birth ceilings and after-the-fact penalties for excess births and do not attempt to change existing cultures' economic patterns, occupational roles, domestic relationships, and community structures.
Instead the reproductive health model tries to provide women with full-range reproductive health care, including access not only to modern contraception but also to disease prevention; prenatal, perinatal, and postnatal health care; and other forms of health care and education that affect reproduction. They are designed to satisfy unmet needs for contraception rather than to force conception on unwilling users, keeping in mind that women in less developed, high-fertility societies routinely say that they would have wanted, on average, about two children fewer than they have. Many of these programs also seek to extend reproductive health care to men, including the provision of male contraception and the prevention of sexually transmitted diseases. Many programs that provide reproductive health care in less developed nations have been inventive in devising new, more effective forms of health care delivery. In Bangladesh, for example, health care workers are aware that village women may have difficulty reaching public clinics or may be prevented from visiting them, and they have developed systems of home delivery of contraceptives and other forms of reproductive health care.
Although reproductive health models of fertility control have avoided many of the ethical problems of earlier programs, they have had other problems. Some nations with conservative administrations, including the United States, have refused to support programs that provide safe abortion services even when those services are recognized by local providers as essential to reproductive health care. Other points of dispute that have been raised, primarily by the Catholic Church, include providing condoms for disease prevention as well as contraception and supplying contraception and other reproductive health services to unmarried adolescents and women. Those issues differ from the ethical dilemmas raised by the earlier programs in that they are politically freighted, occurring at the intersection of conservative political and religious thinking with progressive public health-oriented concerns. Some view the fact that reproductive health programs may involve contraception, abortion, and the provision of services to unmarried persons as an issue of troubling moral significance; for others there seems to be no moral problem.
ETHICAL ISSUES CONCERNING FERTILITY ENCOURAGEMENT
The most thoroughly explored issues in fertility theory are global population growth and ways to control it without violating individual reproductive rights. In some parts of Page 2469 | Top of Articlethe world, however, including Europe and Japan, fertility rates have declined so dramatically that they are well below the replacement rate. Some of the apparent decline is an artifact of later-onset childbearing and longer child-spacing intervals, but some of it is real. Subreplacement societies are “graying,” it often is said, and social security, health insurance, and other social systems are being stressed as low birthrates coupled with much longer average life spans have produced comparatively few children but many elderly people.
The ethical issues that arise in this context have to do with fertility encouragement, usually in preference to more liberal immigration policies, and what measures a society may or should take to increase birthrates, if any, and for what reasons. It is becoming fashionable to speak of “population collapse,” associating the prediction of population decline, particularly in Europe, with predicted economic collapse.
Some countries offer bonuses, generous maternity and paternity leave, or child support for having a baby. Some engage in public advertising that promotes childbearing: “Sterben die Deutschen ausr” (Are the Germans dying out?), asked one German subway poster. Although none of these programs repeats ethical abuses, such as the requirement the former dictator Nicolae Ceauçescu imposed on Romanian women that they bear at least five children, some attempt to influence individual reproductive behavior in many of the same ways advertising tries to influence consumer choice.
The ethical issue here is whether individuals' reproductive lives should be influenced in the same ways and by the same means that manufacturers sell auto-mobiles or laundry soap. There is also the question of whether public service advertising to increase fertility is ethically analogous to public service advertising to decrease fertility, as in “stop at one or two” billboards in Vietnam, soap operas favoring small family size in China, and similar measures in many other countries.
Averting “population collapse” is not the only motivation for a state, ethnic group, or religious organization to encourage fertility. Many earlier societies and some contemporary ones, such as early Maoist China and early twenty-first-century Iraq, have encouraged high fertility rates as a source of military might or productive power: more children mean more soldiers and workers. Some religious groups have encouraged high fertility rates to increase denominational strength, as detractors see it. It may be considered appropriate for some groups that have suffered genocide or other calamities to encourage fertility to recover their demographic strength. Examples include Armenians after their expulsion by the Turks, Jews after the Holocaust, African Americans after slavery, and New World Amerindians after European contact, when indigenous groups in North, Central, and South America were reduced not so much by warfare but by epidemics of European diseases, such as measles, typhus, yellow fever, and smallpox, that in many areas killed 80 to 90 percent of the population or resulted in complete extinction. In what sense a group may or should attempt to regain its earlier population size, when and how compensatory population gain should be measured, and what impact it may have on other groups inhabiting the same region are issues that invite further discussion.
ETHICAL ISSUES CONCERNING TECHNOLOGY IN FERTILITY CONTROL
New reproductive technologies play a major role in issues of fertility control, especially new forms of contraception and pregnancy interruption. Three pose particularly complex ethical issues: male contraception, postconception contraception, and long-acting contraception.
Male Contraception
With the exception of India's vasectomy program, virtually all programs for fertility control have focused on women. Whereas a wide variety of modern contraceptive methods have been developed for women, sexually active males have had only three methods for controlling their contribution to reproduction: withdrawal, condoms, and vasectomy. A number of modern male contraceptive methods are under development, including vas-blocking methods, heat-based methods, and hormonal methods, and several can be expected to reach the market in the early twenty-first century.
These methods raise a variety of ethical issues. Are different degrees of control over whether conception can occur appropriate to nonabstinent males and females? At least in areas where women have free access to it, female-controlled contraception has given women veto power over their own reproduction, something that is often held to be appropriate, because reproduction occurs within women's bodies. Should males also have veto power over reproduction even though it does not affect them physically in the same way? Might the development of effective long-acting but reversible methods of male contraception herald an ethically problematic change in male/female reproductive roles, especially in roles that often are considered essential to female identity?
Postconception Contraception
Among the various methods of female contraception, some function by preventing conception and others by preventing implantation or interrupting an early pregnancy. Generating particularly vigorous ethical controversy have been “morning after” contraceptive modalities, not only “emergency contraception” that is effective for up to 120 hours but also in particular abortifacient methods that interrupt pregnancy at up to seven weeks of gestation.
As with reproductive health programs for fertility control, the problems here are the subject of political dispute involving disagreements between those who oppose abortion altogether and those who do not or who find moral issues of abortion appropriately resolved privately or overridden by other moral concerns. Another issue posed by postconception technologies involves the timing of decisions about pregnancy. Should those decisions be made before conception, when one is not yet pregnant—that is, should they deal with a condition not yet established—or is there a moral and epistemological advantage to allowing conception and pregnancy to occur and then deciding whether to continue it? Opponents of abortion would insist on the former. The latter may be supported on the ground that it gives the woman or couple a more realistic opportunity for full-fledged consent: once pregnancy has begun, she can understand more fully the step she is taking, including the changes it brings about in her body, and then decide whether she wants to continue. Although this issue may seem bizarre to Western theorists of reproduction, it is pressing in countries, such as Soviet-era and post-Soviet Russia, in which abortion has been a principal method of fertility control. The total induced abortion rate for Moscow is about 6 (though for Russia as a whole it is 2.5), and decisions about pregnancy continuation often are made after rather than before the fact.
Long-Acting Contraception
The ethical implications of the difference between short-acting, “time-of-need” contraceptive modalities—such as the condom; the diaphragm; spermicidal foams, gels, and sponges; and other forms that require use at the time of sexual exposure—as distinct from long-acting modalities that have a contraceptive effect over an extended period—such as the IUD, the subdermal implant, and the depot injection—also have been explored inadequately. The central theoretical difference involves the degree of user cooperation required to prevent conception. Short-acting, time-of-need modalities require user awareness and cooperation each time, every time, as do nontechnological methods of contraception, such as withdrawal and the “rhythm method” of scheduled abstinence. In contrast, true long-acting contraception requires no user cooperation beyond the initial emplacement. This difference is obscured, however, by a variety of technologies that have a long-term chemical effect but require repeated dosing, such as oral contraceptives (“the pill”), and by permanent or difficult-to-reverse methods, such as tubal ligation, quinacrine sterilization, and vasectomy.
The ethical issue that arises here concerns whether it is morally appropriate to “reverse the default” in human reproductive biology. In the early twenty-first century sexual contact between a fertile male and a fertile female may permit conception unless that is prevented; if the default were reversed by having long-acting, indwelling but reversible contraception in place and if everybody used it, sexual contact would not permit conception unless that was chosen. The consequences of such a reversal for fertility control are potentially enormous. If everybody did it all the time, that is, used long-acting, reversible contraception except when he or she wanted to have a child, fertility rates would decline dramatically without a violation of reproductive rights.
SOCIETAL INTERESTS IN FERTILITY
The issue of societal interests in individual fertility is of immense complexity. Society in general, that is, the global population as a whole, is composed of individual human beings, all of whom are the product of reproductive activity between earlier human beings—their parents, the providers of the male and female gametes involved. A small proportion of this reproductive activity, at least in the developed world, involves artificial reproductive technologies, such as in vitro fertilization, embryo storage and transfer, surrogacy, and cloning, and some involves arrangements between nonhet-erosexual couples, but most reproductive behavior takes place between a man and a woman, whose reproductive roles are influenced by the wide range of cultural settings in which their conjunction occurs.
The overarching ethical question is what weight the interests of their society or society in general should be given over people's personal choices about reproduction. Should concern about global population growth take precedence over individual reproductive behavior? Should the risks of population decline take priority over individual choice? Are pressures for increased fertility more or less defensible than pressures for fertility limitation? These larger issues invite extended exploration.
Population-control measures are motivated principally by the Malthusian specter of global crowding, which traditionally is formulated as the threat that a population will outrun the carrying capacity of its site, that is, will consume more than can be replaced in its environment and thus eventually will exhaust its resources and die. The urgency of global fertility control often is underestimated by those who confuse declining growth rates with declining growth: growth rates are falling in virtually all areas of the world, but as a result of immense population momentum in the latter decades of the twentieth century, total global population is still increasing rapidly. Nevertheless, the Malthusian specter does not answer the question of whether it is better to have fewer people with a higher standard of living or more people in far more modest circumstances. What should be the aim of population control?
As the philosopher Derek Parfit (1984) has discussed, different future scenarios may involve fewer people with a Page 2471 | Top of Articlehigher quality of life or more people with a lower quality of life, but as long as the quality of life is not so low that life is not worth living, it is not easy to say why a larger population of less fortunate people is not preferable to a smaller population of people with a higher quality of life. Parfit entertains what he calls the “repugnant conclusion” (Parfit 1984, 381) that for a large population with a high quality of life there always could be a much larger population with a much lower quality of life, a life barely worth living, but that such a future would be better.
Similarly fewer people consuming more is not obviously better than more people consuming less in terms of global environmental impact and also is not obviously morally preferable to the opposite situation, assuming that the effect on environmental sustainability is equal. This philosophical puzzle raises deep cultural, political, and religious questions and perhaps will be the central challenge for theorists of fertility control in the future.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Battin, Margaret Pabst. 1997. “Color y cultura: La anticoncepción automática y su impacto en la población urbana negra norteamericana y en la de paises en desarrollo.” Perspectivas Bioéticas en las Américas 2 (1): 64–92.
Battin, Margaret Pabst. 2009. “Population Issues.” In A Companion to Bioethics, 2nd ed., edited by Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer, 163–77. Maiden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Bongaarts, John. 1994. “Population Policy Options in the Developing World.” Science 263 (5148): 771–76.
Bongaarts, John. 1997. “The Role of Family Planning Programmes in Contemporary Fertility Transitions.” In The Continuing Demographic Transition, edited by Gavin W. Jones, Robert M. Douglas, and John C. Caldwell, 422–44. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bongaarts, John, and Judith Bruce. 1995. “The Causes of Unmet Need for Conception and the Social Content of Services.” Studies in Family Planning 26 (2): 57–75.
Cohen, Joel E. 1995. How Many People Can the Earth Support? New York: Norton.
Cook, Noble David. 1998. Born to Die: Disease and New World Conquest, 1492–1650. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Dixon-Mueller, Ruth. 1993. Population Policy and Women's Rights: Transforming Reproductive Choice. Westport, CT: Praeger.
Ehrlich, Paul R. 1968. The Population Bomb. New York: Ballantine.
Ehrlich, Paul R.; Anne H. Ehrlich; and Gretchen C. Daily. 1995. The Stork and the Plow: The Equity Answer to the Human Dilemma. New York: Putnam.
Gardiner, Stephen M. 2001. “The Real Tragedy of the Commons.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 30 (4): 387–416.
Hardin, Garrett James. 1993. Living within Limits: Ecology, Economics, and Population Taboos. New York: Oxford University Press.
Harris, John, and Søren Holm, eds. 1998. The Future of Human Reproduction: Ethics, Choice, and Regulation. New York: Oxford University Press.
Hartmann, Betsy. 1995. Reproductive Rights and Wrongs: The Global Politics of Population Control. Rev. ed. Boston: South End.
MacDonald, Peter. 2000. “Gender Equity in Theories of Fertility Transition.” Population and Development Review 26 (3): 427–39.
Macklin, Ruth. 1981. “Ethics, Effectiveness, and Efficiency in Population Programs.” In Ethical Issues of Population Aid: Culture, Economics, and International Assistance, edited by Daniel Callahan and Philip G. Clark, 333–60. New York: Irvington.
Maguire, Daniel C. 2003. Sacred Rights: The Case for Contraception and Abortion in the Worldí Religions. New York: Oxford University Press.
Malthus, Thomas Robert. 1960 [1798]. On Population, edited by Gertrude Himmelfarb. New York: Modern Library.
Nussbaum, Martha Craven. 1999. Sex and Social Jtistice. New York: Oxford University Press.
Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon.
Paul VI. 1968. On the Regulation of Birth, Humanae vitae: Encyclical Letter, Pope Paul VI, July 25, 1968. Washington, DC: US Catholic Conference.
Sathar, Zeba Ayesha, and James F. Phillips, eds. 2001. Fertility Transition in South Asia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as Freedom. New York: Knopf.
Sen, Gita; Adrienne Germain; and Lincoln C. Chen, eds. 1994. Population Policies Reconsidered: Health, Empowerment, and Rights. Boston, MA: Harvard University Press.
Simon, Julian Lincoln. 1981. The Ultimate Resource. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
United Nations. 1995. “Program of Action of the 1994 International Conference on Population and Development.” Population and Development Review 21 (1): 187–213.
United Nations Department of International Economic and Social Affairs. 1987–1990. World Population Policies. New York: United Nations.
United Nations Population Fund. 2002. State of the World Population 2002: People, Poverty, and Possibility. New York: Author.
Veatch, Robert M. 1977. “Governmental Population Incentives: Ethical Issues at Stake.” Studies in Family Planning 8 (4): 100–108.
Margaret Pabst Battin (2004, 2014)
Professor, Department of Philosophy and Division of
Medical Ethics and Humanities, University of Utah
Source Citation
Gale Document Number: GALE|CX3727400504