There Is No Justification for Legalizing Euthanasia

Citation metadata

Author: Peter C. Glover
Editor: Noël Merino
Date: 2012
Publisher: Gale, a Cengage Company
Series: Current Controversies
Document Type: Viewpoint essay
Length: 1,275 words
Content Level: (Level 3)
Lexile Measure: 1040L

Document controls

Main content

Full Text: 

Article Commentary

Peter C. Glover, "Euthanasia: Can It Ever Be Right to Legalise It?," Catholic Insight, vol. 17, no. 2, February 2009, pp. 8-9. All rights reserved. Reproduced by permission.

Peter C. Glover is a British writer specializing in politics, the media, and cultural affairs.

The courts in the English-speaking world have recently witnessed a number of high-profile and distressing cases where individuals have argued both for the 'right to die' and even the 'right to live' in the event of incapacitation. But it was perhaps in the troubling case of the young American woman Terri Schiavo that the issues surrounding euthanasia have been most hotly debated. This was a case that, like no other, split the conscience of a nation, causing a public debate which cut deep into the American psyche and exposed the core ethical arguments surrounding the whole morality of euthanasia or assisted suicide as never before.

At the heart of the debate was not only the 'human right' to choose death, but the 'right' for society, in general, to be complicit in its acquiescence, hence legally.

The Terminology of Suicide and Euthanasia

Before we get to grips with the issue itself, however, it is important, if we wish to avoid the confusion that often derails genuine debate, to clarify our terminology.

  1. Suicide—is self-killing, some would say self-murder.
  2. Assisted suicide—involves enlisting the aid of another person, often a doctor, to end one's own life. Those 'assisting' provide the means of death but do not take part in the killing directly.
  3. Euthanasia—occurs when someone other than the 'patient'—a doctor, nurse or someone else—performs an action, such as a lethal injection, which brings about death.
  4. Passive euthanasia—occurs when the withdrawal of medical assistance or life-sustaining treatment leads 'naturally' to the death of the patient. This term is seldom used because of the near universal agreement that it is, and has always been, a justifiable treatment ethically (i.e. allowing 'nature' to take its course).

Let me state my case here bluntly: with the exception of no. 4, which has been largely unquestioned common medical practice for centuries, none of the other three (suicide, assisted suicide or euthanasia) has any moral justification in the light of sound reason and/or medical science.

The Judeo-Christian worldview is a well-reasoned pattern of belief in which the sanctity of life is given moral substance.

I am opposed to euthanasia in all its forms, not just because I, as a Christian, believe the Creator God is demonstrably opposed to it, making no provision for it in His revealed will to mankind and through the teaching of the Catholic Church, but also because the biblical and Church teaching, which is not the subject of this particular article, is wholly supported by every ethical, philosophical and reasoned argument available. I mention my biblical worldview here with good reason. All too often, the issue of worldview is obscured in the public debate. Indeed, many Christians even feel it judicious not to mention it at all, as if the assumption is that the secular person, unlike the Christian, does not possess a 'worldview' or cultural or philosophical spectacles through which he views the world. Nothing could be further from the truth! It is just a case of articulating what one's worldview is, and how it affects and underpins the views or opinions being expressed.

This is no secondary matter whenever any moral issue is being discussed. When all is said and done, the Judeo-Christian worldview is a well-reasoned pattern of belief in which the sanctity of life is given moral substance. Those who criticise such a worldview ought to be called upon to articulate and uphold their own.

The Moral Gold Standard

The advantage here is that we can point to a 'gold standard' of moral right or wrong—in fact the moral gold standard which is the foundation of Western civilization's Judeo-Christian heritage. Those who hold secular and liberal privatised worldviews often struggle to sustain them. While the biblical and conservative worldview is focused on the higher good of the community, one usually finds that the secular liberal focuses on the rights of the individual. The reality is, however, that one must outweigh the other. And the Bible as well as historic tradition dictates that it must be the higher good of the community that wins out.

Having made this important point, however, in this article I intend to equip the ordinary Catholic Christian with insight into the case against the legalisation of euthanasia from a secular perspective to reinforce the biblical argument.

The more difficult but humane solution to human suffering is to address the problem, not get rid of the human.

Here, in a nutshell, are the very practical and key arguments against legalising euthanasia/assisted suicide in any form:

  1. A request for assisted suicide is typically a cry for help. In reality it is typically a call for counselling, assistance and positive alternatives as solutions to very real problems.
  2. Suicidal intent is typically transient. Of those who attempt suicide, fewer than 4% go on to kill themselves in the next five years; less than 11% will commit suicide over the next 35 years.
  3. Terminally ill patients who desire death are typically depressed—and depression is treatable. In one study, 24% of those desiring death had clinical depression.
  4. Pain is controllable. The array of treatments to control pain (palliative care) is vast and impressive today. Often the person seeking death does not need assistance to commit suicide but a doctor better trained in palliative care. The Nightingale Alliance states that 95% of all pain is controllable and the other 5% can be reduced to a tolerable level.
  5. Legalising voluntary euthanasia almost always means legalising non-voluntary euthanasia. In America, for instance, state courts have consistently ruled that if competent people have a right, then incompetent people must be 'given' the same 'right.' It is highly likely that the British courts would rule the same way.
  6. The Netherlands' experience in legalising voluntary assisted suicide for those with terminal illness has spread to include non-voluntary euthanasia for people with no terminal illness. Half of the killings in the Netherlands are now non-voluntary and a 'culture of death,' admitted as such privately by many Dutch doctors, has now taken root there. It has become a common legal 'solution' for those with mental illness, permanent disability, and even old age.
  7. You don't solve problems by getting rid of the people to whom the problems happen. The more difficult but humane solution to human suffering is to address the problem, not get rid of the human....

No Justification for Legal Suicide

[There] are no scientific, medical or ethical reasons why any of us, not just Catholic Christians, should condone or support the legalisation of euthanasia in society.

No one can prevent someone, intent on the act, from taking out a revolver and blowing his brains out, or administering a lethal dose of drugs to himself or another. But that is not the issue here.

The issue here is whether there are sound reasons why a society and a nation should acquiesce in the process by legalising it. If we are intent on protecting the weak and retaining our current culture of life, in the Hippocratic tradition, then we must face whether we would rather introduce a culture of uncertainty and of death as has happened in the Netherlands. A culture where we can never be sure whether someone, somewhere, believes that our 'quality of life' is such that the world—according to their worldview—would be better off without us or those we love, brings dreadful uncertainty and immense unnecessary suffering.

Source Citation

Source Citation   

Gale Document Number: GALE|EJ3010035408